Kantianism and Thomistic Personalism
on the Human Person:
Self-Legislator or Self-Determiner?
John F. X. Knasas
Center for
Thomistic Studies University of St. Thomas Houston, Texas, U.S.A.
In last year’s Thomistic Personalism session there was some discussion about whether
John Paul II grounded human dignity in a Kantian way, viz., emphasizing the person as an end unto
itself. I was one of the discussants that expressed the danger of that liaison.
And so after Prof. Hayden Lemmons’ kind invitation to speak at this year’s session, I
thought that I would take the opportunity to discuss the relations between Kant
and Aquinas
on the topic of the philosophical basis of human dignity. Since these sessions
are also devoted to the thought of John Paul II, then I will also consider his remarks on Kant’s
ethics.
I
In his Groundwork for
the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant investigates the source for the appearance
of moral necessity, or obligation. I summarize Kant’s analysis as follows. Kant
begins with the "good will." The good will is the will that acts for
the sake of the law alone and not for any benefit derived from following the law. But
what does fidelity to the law mean? It means fidelity to what characterizes
law. And what is that? It is "universality." A law makes
universal claims: no one, no where can do such and
such. Next, this fidelity to universality is articulated in terms of the categorical imperative: do only what
you are able to universalize. Somewhat similarly we say in Christianity: Love
your neighbor as yourself. But Kant pushes the analysis further. Why
the categorical imperative?
For Kant the categorical imperative is grounded on the idea
of a rational being as an end in itself. How so? Well, reflect upon what
violating the imperative
means. If I am willing to say that the proscription of lying is not universal,
then I am saying that in some circumstances I can be lied to. Now for Kant there is something
insulting with that thought. The insult is that I am being treated as a mere
means to someone else’s end. To Kant that treatment is a striking
violation of our dignity. Our dignity, then, is that we are ends unto
ourselves.
But Kant’s analysis continues. That we are ends means that we
must regard ourselves as self-legislating. Kant translates this idea of a
self-legislator into the idea of the autonomous will. Such a will is
absolutely free in that it takes no cues for its exercise from anything else.
In other words, not even knowledge of the moral law precedes the will. Such a
reference for the will would encroach on the will’s autonomy.
If I have understood Kant, I wonder if his analysis cuts off
the branch on which it is sitting. The analysis is supposed to explain the
appearance of moral
necessity, or obligation. But, in my opinion, the analysis concludes to a will
so autonomous that it is not bound by anything, including the categorical imperative. I know that
Kant acknowledges that the categorical imperative is the "supreme
law" of a good will and that the imperative is compatible with the will’s autonomy.
Yet, I insist on asking "How?." Kant says
that heteronomy exists when the will seeks the moral law in the character of its object. But is not
the supreme law, the categorical imperative, a response to our character as
ends unto ourselves? It seems so. It does no good to reply that heteronomy
only results when the will is related to the character of something other than itself. For the character of
the will
itself is in some sense other than the will insofar as the will is of such a character. In sum, the
categorical imperative expresses to the will the marching orders of the character of
the will. How is this situation compatible with Kant’s talk about the autonomy
of the will and talk of the will legislating its laws? The will seems
to be not autonomous in respect to its character, and its laws seem to be
dictated not by itself but the characterimposed
categorical imperative. Hence, in my opinion, the only way that Kant can avoid
inconsistency is to admit that the will is so autonomous that it self-legislates even the
categorical imperative. And if self-legislation is the correct conclusion of
Kant’s logic, then what happens to moral necessity? Can a true creator of
legislation be considered as genuinely bound by that legislation? Is not the
idea of a self-legislator a contradiction in terms? In sum, what is arbitrarily
asserted can always be arbitrarily denied, even by the original asserter.
Hence, Kant brings the project of ethics to an impasse. Insofar as he explains
obligation in a way that extinguishes obligation, then to preserve obligation
we have to leave obligation unexplained. Ethics has lost its
future.
II
Aquinas
also employs human freedom to evoke obligation. At Summa Contra Gentiles III, 112, Aquinas explains why in God’s
providence God governs rational creatures for their own sake, not in
subordination to some other creature. Aquinas thinking here is most relevant
for human ethics, because if God has to treat us in a particular way because we
are free, then a fortiori and for the
same reason we should treat each other similarly. Aquinas says:
… the very way in which the intellectual creature was made,
according as it is master of its acts, demands providential care whereby this
creature may provide for itself, on its own behalf; while the way in which
other things were created, things which have no dominion over their acts, shows
this fact, that they are cared for, not for their own sake, but as subordinated
to others. That which is moved only by another being has the formal character
of an instrument, but that which acts of itself has the essential character of
a principal agent. Now, an instrument is not valued for its own sake, but as
useful to a principal agent. Hence it must be that all the careful work that is
devoted to instruments is actually done for the sake of the agent, as for an
end, but what is done for the principal agent, either by himself or by another,
is for his own sake, because he is the principal agent. Therefore, intellectual
creatures are so controlled by God, as objects of care for their own sakes;
while other creatures are subordinated, as it were, to the rational creatures.
Aquinas uses the freedom of the rational creature to argue
that it should be treated for its own sake. In other words, Aquinas grounds the
dignity of the human on its freedom of will. In Groundwork Kant argued in opposite fashion. He concluded to the
autonomy of will from our being ends unto ourselves. No conflict exists here
because Kant is just proceeding analytically to what Aquinas uses as a starting
point. It remains for both that freedom is a principle of morals.
Yet each understands freedom differently. For Aquinas the
free agent is not a self-legislator but a self-determiner, an agent that acts
through its consent. Unlike Kant’s autonomous will, which is incompatible with
direction by reason, the freedom of a self-determiner is compatible with
rational direction. In fact, Aquinas indicates the object of that direction in
another argument of Ch. 112.
. . . it is evident that all parts are ordered to the
perfection of the whole, since a whole does not exist for the sake of its
parts, but, rather, the parts are for the whole. Now intellectual natures have
a closer relationship to a whole than do other natures; indeed, each
intellectual substance is, in a way, all things. For it may comprehend the
entirety of being through its intellect [inquantum totius entis comprehensiva est suo intellectu]; on he other hand, every other substance has only a particular
share in being. Therefore, other substances may fittingly be providentially
cared for by God for the sake of intellectual substances.
The human as an intellector of
being is what directs God’s providence to govern the human for its own sake. This
same understanding of ourselves and our fellows should be what merits the
respect and solicitude of our free will. To understand Aquinas’ argument two
points are important. The notion of being, the ratio entis , is not just any whole or entirety. Being is a
transcendental analogon. As such it is a commonality,
or intelligibility, that implicitly but actually, contains the different
perfections of all conceivable things. This thinking about being follows from
Aquinas’ repeated assertions that addition to being is not from outside as is
the case with the addition of species to a genus. Rather, addition to being is via the differences expressing what is
actually but implicitly contained by the notion. Hence, the ratio entis is
not just any whole; it is the whole that contains the perfections of all
things. In sum, the ratio entis is also the good, the ratio boni.
Second, following Aristotle Aquinas views cognition, both
sensory and intellectual, as an especially intimate becoming of the known by
the knower. Knowers have an "amplitude" and "extension" of
form over matter that allows them to receive the very form of the thing known
without detriment to themselves. As so conformed to the known, the knower is
suitably equipped to produce it as the term of the knower’s cognitive
activities.
These two points mean that in the human person understood as,
what I will call, an "intellector of
being," we confront an especially intense presence of the good. It is no
wonder that even God relates to the rational creature in a providence that
governs the rational creature for its own sake. So in Aquinas freedom is guided
freedom. Reason addresses freedom with facts that include moral necessity. Our
fellows are intellectors of being and being is the
good. These facts are crucial for understanding Aquinas’ seminal article on the
basis of natural law ethics in his Summa Theologiae I-II, 94, 2c. For Aquinas the future of
ethics lies in being faithful to these facts in all of our various activities.
In contrast, for Kant, if I have understood him, no facts can address our
freedom. Any such address would compromise the autonomy of the will and Kant’s
understanding of the will as selflegislating.
Finally the Thomistic notion of human
freedom is not only compatible with rational direction, it is also compatible
with the phenomena that Kant analyzes for his purposes. This point is important
for noticing that Kant’s analysis seems to commit a non-sequitur. That I ought to be treated as an end does not
strictly entail that I ought to be regarded as self-legislating. It suffices
that I be thought of as self-determining. Such an agent is also an end. Your
capacity for self-determination forces me to respect you for yourself and so as
an end. The idea of being self-determining also explains the insult that we
feel in being lied to. By the lie we are enlisted in a project for which we did
not give our consent. So, Aquinas can take the best features of Kant’s
position, viz., human dignity and its connection with human freedom, but parlay
them so that they do not become antinomies. As self-determination human freedom
still is a ground for human dignity.
III
I now turn to Karol Wojtyla’s
comments on Kant as they appear in various articles collected in Person and Community: Selected Essays
translated by Teresa Sandok. Wojtyla
is quite aware that in Kant the will does not act on the basis of a good
proposed by reason. This point is quite clear from his summary of Kant in the
article "In Search of the Basis of Perfectionism in Ethics." Even
though the terminology of self-determination is employed to describe Kant, this
phrase does not indicate the offering of alternatives by reason to the will, as
the phrase did indicate in my above use of it. So Wojtyla
notes that for Kant "ethics as a science can be based only on a form
supplied by practical reason. This is the form of universal legislation, which
appears a priori in consciousness in
the guise of an imperative." Furthermore, "the experience of an
imperative is linked, in Kant’s view with the experience of freedom. All
determination is an actual exclusion of free will." Hence, ". . . we
must seek morality, or the socalled ethical content
of consciousness, in the transphenomenal homo noumenon.
To it alone belongs autonomy, or freedom." In still other words,
When practical reason is directed solely and exclusively by
this [a priori] form, the experience
of pure duty arises in practical consciousness, and in this pure duty
"supersensible" humanity (homo noumenon) simultaneously experiences its total freedom.
Duty, thus understood, is free of all determination from without, from the side
of the phenomenal world; it is subject to determination only from within, from
the side of consciousness. Consequently, pure duty involves the experience of
self-determination, the experience of freedom – an experience that gives
consciousness a certain nonsensory satisfaction.
A few lines later, Wojtyla claims
that for Kant "it is within this experience [of freedom or
self-determination} that morality is contained."
I understand these remarks to repeat the reduction mentioned
in my earlier description of Kant. Namely: first duty, then to law, to
universality, to person as end unto itself, and finally to autonomy. Upon
reaching autonomy, however, I and Wojtyla criticize
Kant for different things. I criticize Kantian autonomy for a resultant
arbitrariness. Wojtyla criticisizes
it for being so contra to our evident
experience. If I understand him, Wojtyla develops
this criticism along two lines. First, in his article "The Separation of
Experience from the Act in Ethics," Woytyla
repeats the description of Kant’s ethics that he gave in the "Basis of
Perfectionism" essay. He then observes
Given such assumptions, the moral activity of the will
requires a complete turning away from all goods. As long as the will in its
activity strives for any good whatsoever, even a good of the objectively
highest order, we are not dealing with morality. Such a position, however,
which results from an unconditional break with experience, does not embrace any
concrete human action within its scope. A concrete action by its very nature
aims at some good, and so in every real human action arising from the will we
must encounter an inclination toward some good.
Later Wojtyla describes this result
as a separation of the logical and psychological aspects of the one ethical act
and says that "such a split, however, is at flagrant odds with
experience."
Second, again in the "Separation of Experience"
essay, Wojtyla also criticizes the degradation of the
will in Kant’s position. Because of the turning away of the will from all
goods, the will as we experience it, i.e., as in the phenomenal order, should
be rendered dumb and ineffectual. It should lose its evidential character as a
principle of action. He says "The will, in Kant’s view, is devoid of any
innate dynamism of its own. This is because the will has no proper object to
which it would naturally turn in its activity, but is in each case subject to
the motives that practical reason gives it." In the essay entitled
"The Will in the Analysis of the Ethical Act," Wojtyla
says that "for Kant the will is not merely under the direction of
practical reason but is completely identified with it."(4) Wojtyla emphasizes that Kant’s understanding is not only
one-sided but ". . . does not square with experience." Hence, Wojtyla praises current psychological studies that
corroborate a more traditional understanding of the will as a faculty and thus
as having a causal-efficient character. Here he mentions Aquinas and describes
Aquinas’ understanding of the will.
According to St. Thomas, this process occurs as it does
because the will’s whole natural dynamism has a distinct inclination that
arises from the will’s own nature, the will shares in the act of command, for
it provides the power upon which reason relies in formulating the content of a
command. As far as human activity in general is concerned, the will appears
there as a faculty that acts in conjunction with reason – rather than one that
merely submits to the causality of motives.
And later,
The activity of the will is understood by St. Thomas as
having two basic sources of actualization. One is the nature of the will
itself, for the will is by nature an appetite (appetitus), and so it exhibits an
inclination toward everything that is in any way good (bonum in communi). Because this appetitive
inclination constitutes the very nature of the will, the will does not need any
external causalefficient impulses to operate. . . . By virtue of this nature, the will is itself already
a causal-efficient source of impulse in the human being, impulses that have
various goods as their object. That which St. Thomas calls motio quoad exercitium
comes from the will’s natural motion.
The second source of the will’s actuation Wojtyla
describes this way:
Reason’s task, in cooperating with the desire for good that
naturally resides in the will, is to objectify for the will the true goodness
of those goods and thereby direct the inclination of the will.
. . . St. Thomas calls it motio quoad specificationem, . . .
Fellow Thomists might want to disagree about the first source
of the will’s actualization, viz., the will’s very nature or constitution
understood as an inclination to the good in common. For textual reasons they
might wonder if volition itself is ignited by the intellect’s presentation of
the ratio entis
understood as the ratio boni? Fellow Thomists might also wonder if Wojtyla’s first source of the will’s actualization is
making a concession to Kantian transcendental thinking. Nevertheless, for
purposes of grounding human dignity, Wojtyla’s
thinking is close enough to Aquinas’ noted reflections in S.C.G. III, 112. An intimacy exists not only between knower and
known but also between willer and willed. At S.T. I, 59, 2, Aquinas notes that not by
assimilation but by inclination the will extends itself to that which is
outside it. And so just as the person as an intellector
of being assumes a dignity, so too does the person as a willer
of the ratio boni,
which is being once again under another guise.
Unfortunately I do not find Wojtyla
making this connection between willer of the good and
dignity nor the connection between intellector of
being and dignity, though he is aware of both characterizations of the human
person. Yet such connections would go a long way to explain why we should
pursue an ethics of perfectionism. In regard to such an ethics in both
Aristotle and Aquinas, Wojtyla emphasizes the
understanding of the good as what perfects and is suitable to the nature of the
thing. But if the thing is ourselves, then a more basic issue is why we should
treasure and cherish ourselves. In my opinion, the heightened presence of the ratio entis in
the activities of intellection and willing speak to this issue. In short,
goodness as a formal cause presupposes goodness as a final cause, goodness as a
point of attraction. The above two understandings of the human person convey
enough luster to the human such that practical reason can then formulate a
command to be respectful and solicitous.
IV
In conclusion, both Kant and Aquinas ground human dignity
upon human freedom. But both understand the human freedom differently. For
Kant, human freedom is self-legislating and so exercised without rational
direction. I argued that this conception of the will shuts down the ethical
project because the will is so autonomous that any legislating is only a
charade. Moral necessity, or obligation, disappears. Wojtyla
argued that Kant conception of the will makes the will so autonomous that it
becomes completely noumenal and so ceases to be
something experiential. Nevertheless, Wojtyla also
notes that experiential psychology continues to find the will active and causal
contra Kant’s insistence that in the
experiential order the will is motive saturated. In contrast to Kant, Aquinas
understands human freedom to be self-determining. By
"self-determining" I mean acting from one’s consent. The Thomistic
notion of freedom is compatible with rational direction. The direction
consists, for example, in the human understood as an intellector
of being or as a willer of the good, though neither
seem to be exploited by Wojtyla.